Langage et concepts catégoriques pour les mathématiques et l’informatique
This is a wiki for a course at the MSTII "École doctorale" of Grenoble.
Students are encouraged to participate by extending the wiki, adding proofs, corrections for exercices etc. To be able to modify the wiki, you need to register (upper right corner). Please use your real name...
News
Courses are on wednesdays morning, 9'00 to 12'00 in room F218 at the "UFR IMAG".
- first course on the 25th of February: categories, functors, natural transformations.
Basic Concepts
Categories
Definition. A concrete category is given by:
- a collection of sets with structure,
- for any pair of such sets, a set of morphisms preserving the structure.
Morphisms should compose, and the identity should be a morphism.
This definition is a little informal, but here are some examples:
- Grp: groups and group morphisms
- Top: topological spaces and continuous functions
- Ring: rings and rings morphisms
- Vect: vectors spaces and linear maps
- CPO: CPOs and continuous functions
- ...
- Set: sets and functions (ie sets with no structures, and arbitrary functions)
Generalizing the definition, we obtain the official definition of category:
Definition. A category is given by:
- a collection of objects, (notation: )
- for each pair of objects, a collection of morphisms from to , (notation )
- for any object , a special morphism
- for all objects , a composition ,
such that:
- whenever it makes sense.
All concrete categories are categories, and here are some examples that are not obviously concrete:
- Graph: graphs and graph morphisms
- Rel: sets and relations
- Set×Set: pairs of sets, pairs of functions
- Set: opposite of Set
- P, whenever (P,<) is a preorder (at most one morphism between objects)
- M, whenever (M,e,×) is a monoid (a single object)
We sometimes write instead of .
In a given category , there are analogues of the notions of injective and surjective functions in Set. We will see that on concrete categories, they are actually slightly more general. The idea of injectivity gives rise to monomorphisms, and surjectivity gives rise to epimorphisms.
Definition.
A morphism is a monomorphism iff for all object and morphisms , we have implies .
The morphism is an epimorphism when it is a monomorphism in . Explicitly, when for all object and morphisms , we have implies .
isomorphism
Exercice
- Prove that in Set, epic is equivalent to surjective and monic is equivalent to injective.
- Prove the same thing in Ab, the category of commutative groups. (One thing is not obvious.)
- Prove the same thing in Grp, the category of (non necessarily commutative) groups. (One thing is not obvious at all.)
- Prove that is an epimorphism in the category of rings with multiplicative neutral. (Note that it is not surjective.)
- In Set, we saw that f is a monic iff , where 1 is any singleton set. Can you find a set C such that f is epic iff ?
- In Group, can you find an object playing a role similar to 1, ie a group G s.t. f is monic iff . (We saw that we cannot use the singleton group ({e},e,×) to do that...)
Functors
Informally, a functor is a map between two categories which somehow preserves the structure of categories (namely, composition).
Definition. A functor from a category to a category , noted , is given by:
- a map which sends every object of to an object in , and
- a map which sends every morphism in , to a morphism in ,
such that:
- preserves identities, i.e., , and
- preserves composition: .
Exercice
- Take a functor , three morphisms in , and , , . When , can we say something interesting about , and ?
- Do functors preserve monomorphisms? Do functors preserve epimorphisms?
- Let F be a functor and F(f) = g, if g is a mono (resp. epi), is f a mono (resp. epi)?
If not, try to find some simple and natural condition on the functor to make that true.
Answer
- No, since and may not even compose! This is the case when has type , and , with collapsing and (i.e., ).
- Functors in general do not preserve mono- nor epimorphisms. We build a counter-example for monomorphisms. Let be the category with two objects and , and exactly one morphism . This is a preorder, so is monic. Now take with two objects and , exactly one morphism , and one extra morphism , different from the identity. Because of , yet , is not monic in . The functor which sends to , to and in to in , does not preserve monomorphisms.
- In general, the answer is (again) no. For monos, take for example the functor which sends to the identity. Yet, when is faithful, then is monic (or epic).
Definition. A functor is faithful when, for any two morphisms , implies ( is injective on morphisms).
Definition. A functor is full when, for any two objects , if is a morphism , then there exists with ( is surjective on morphisms).
Exercice
Find an "interesting" functor from Set to Group.
Answer Let be the functor which sends:
- every set to the free group generated by , and
- every function to a group morphism defined by: .
Exercice
If is a locally small category and A one of its objects, let . Show that this operation from objects of to sets can be extended into a contravariant functor to Set.
Answer Let be a morphism in , then is expected to be a function from the set to the set . We can take, for any morphism : .
This extends to a contravariant functor, since and .
Natural Transformations
Definition. Let and be two functors . A natural transformation from to is given by:
- a morphism in for every object in ,
- such that, for any morphism , we have .
Exercice
If is the set of permutation of a (finite) set X; and the set of its linear orderings, we have where . Thus, there is a bijection (iso in Set) between P(X) and L(X).
- Show that we can extend P and L to functors from B to Set, where B is the category of finite sets and bijections,
- Show that there can be no natural transformation from P to L,
- Conclude that there is no natural isomorphism between P and L.
Limits and colimits
One of the main thrusts of category theory is to define concepts by their properties rather than by explicit construction. In general this is just called abstraction, but in good cases, concepts are defined by their properties, at least canonically if not uniquely.
The chief example of this is binary products in Set. The product of two sets and is generally thought of as the set of pairs with and . But strictly speaking, or rather set-theoretically speaking, one has to construct it by cautious use of the axioms of Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory.
Instead, in any category , for any objects and categorists put:
Definition. A product of and is an object with arrows
such that for any object and arrows
there exists a unique arrow making the diagram
commute, i.e., and .
The standard constructions in Set all have this property, and
all the non-standard ones you can think of also do, e.g., the set of
pairs with and .
Conversely, any set with this property is as good as any other construction of .
Products are determined canonically by this property property. We will give a more precise meaning to this in later lectures; for now we just state:
Lemma.
For any other product
of
and , there is a unique isomorphism pair such that the diagrams
commute.
Adjunctions
First examples and definition
So-called free constructions in algebra: monoid, group, etc
Their universal property, the underlying functor
The isomorphism between hom-sets
Its naturality
Definition
On to the definition with and
The simplicity behind definitions:2-categories and adjunctions therein
Definition of 2-categories
String diagrams
CAT as a 2-category
Adjunctions in a 2-category
Other basic examples
====Discussion: any syntax defines the free something==== The issue of variable binding.
Adjunction between partial orders = Galois connection
and in logic
Sets/graphs and categories
Monads and resolutions
Definition of a monad
String diagrams
Every adjunction yields a monad
Example of monoids again: resolutions
Monadic adjunctions
The category of resolutions
Eilenberg-Moore is terminal
Kleisli is initial
Monadic adjunctions
Algebraic theories
Properties
Composing adjunctions
Preservation of limits/colimits
Freyd's existence theorem
Beck's monadicity theorem
Course Complements, references
One of the best books about category theory is
- Saunder MacLane, "Categories for the Working Mathematician".
It is a little "dry", in the sense that learning categories from it is not the easiest task on earth, but it still is one of the best references.
I haven't really read it carefully, but here is what Wikipedia has to say on category theory.